How strong is the axiom of well-ordered choice? Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 23:30 UTC (7:30pm US/Eastern)Why is the Axiom of Well-ordered Choice not strong enough to prove Zorn's Lemma?No uncountable ordinals without the axiom of choice?Axiom of choice , Hartogs ordinals, well-ordering principleWhich sets are well-orderable without Axiom of Choice?Well-orderings of $mathbb R$ without Choice“There is no well-ordered uncountable set of real numbers”Axiom of choice and the well ordering principleThe class of well-founded sets satisfies the axiom of foundation and the axiom of choiceAxiom of Choice is equivalent to Well-ordering Theorem: Hrbacek, Jech - “Introduction to Set Theory”the power set of every well-ordered set is well-ordered implies well orderingHow strong are weak choice principles?

Can a Knight grant Knighthood to another?

Normal Operator || T^2|| = ||T||^2

Does using the Inspiration rules for character defects encourage My Guy Syndrome?

What is the ongoing value of the Kanban board to the developers as opposed to management

FME Console for testing

Putting Ant-Man on house arrest

Raising a bilingual kid. When should we introduce the majority language?

How was Lagrange appointed professor of mathematics so early?

Why are two-digit numbers in Jonathan Swift's "Gulliver's Travels" (1726) written in "German style"?

Can gravitational waves pass through a black hole?

Why does BitLocker not use RSA?

Are Flameskulls resistant to magical piercing damage?

What is the evidence that custom checks in Northern Ireland are going to result in violence?

Why isn't everyone flabbergasted about Bran's "gift"?

Why not use the yoke to control yaw, as well as pitch and roll?

Like totally amazing interchangeable sister outfit accessory swapping or whatever

Coin Game with infinite paradox

How to leave only the following strings?

How to ask rejected full-time candidates to apply to teach individual courses?

What's the connection between Mr. Nancy and fried chicken?

Why does my GNOME settings mention "Moto C Plus"?

What documents does someone with a long-term visa need to travel to another Schengen country?

Sorting the characters in a utf-16 string in java

Why these surprising proportionalities of integrals involving odd zeta values?



How strong is the axiom of well-ordered choice?



Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara
Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 23:30 UTC (7:30pm US/Eastern)Why is the Axiom of Well-ordered Choice not strong enough to prove Zorn's Lemma?No uncountable ordinals without the axiom of choice?Axiom of choice , Hartogs ordinals, well-ordering principleWhich sets are well-orderable without Axiom of Choice?Well-orderings of $mathbb R$ without Choice“There is no well-ordered uncountable set of real numbers”Axiom of choice and the well ordering principleThe class of well-founded sets satisfies the axiom of foundation and the axiom of choiceAxiom of Choice is equivalent to Well-ordering Theorem: Hrbacek, Jech - “Introduction to Set Theory”the power set of every well-ordered set is well-ordered implies well orderingHow strong are weak choice principles?










11












$begingroup$


I sometimes see references to the "Axiom of Well-Ordered Choice," but I'm not sure how strong it is. It states that every well-ordered family of sets has a choice function.



By "well-ordered family," I don't mean that the sets within the family are well-ordered, but that the family must index all the sets within the family by some ordinal.



How strong is this axiom? Can it prove the Hahn-Banach theorem, the ultrafilter lemma, anything about measurable sets, etc? Does it have any implications about what sets can be well-ordered (the reals for instance), or perhaps prove anything about the Hartogs number of sets, etc?



Does anyone have a reference for this?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    ...isn't this axiom a consequence of ZF? One can choose the (well-defined, since it's well-ordered) lexicographically least element of each set in the family...
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Mar 8 at 20:46






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    That is a family of well-ordered sets, not a well-ordered family of (arbitrary sets).
    $endgroup$
    – Mike Battaglia
    Mar 8 at 20:47










  • $begingroup$
    Ahh, I missed that distinction. Thank you!
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Mar 8 at 20:50










  • $begingroup$
    I've never seen this axiom before. Does the family itself need to be a set or can it be a proper class?
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Shore
    Mar 8 at 20:55










  • $begingroup$
    Google suggests this: settheory.mathtalks.org/andreas-blass-well-ordered-choice
    $endgroup$
    – Carl Mummert
    Mar 8 at 20:56















11












$begingroup$


I sometimes see references to the "Axiom of Well-Ordered Choice," but I'm not sure how strong it is. It states that every well-ordered family of sets has a choice function.



By "well-ordered family," I don't mean that the sets within the family are well-ordered, but that the family must index all the sets within the family by some ordinal.



How strong is this axiom? Can it prove the Hahn-Banach theorem, the ultrafilter lemma, anything about measurable sets, etc? Does it have any implications about what sets can be well-ordered (the reals for instance), or perhaps prove anything about the Hartogs number of sets, etc?



Does anyone have a reference for this?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$











  • $begingroup$
    ...isn't this axiom a consequence of ZF? One can choose the (well-defined, since it's well-ordered) lexicographically least element of each set in the family...
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Mar 8 at 20:46






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    That is a family of well-ordered sets, not a well-ordered family of (arbitrary sets).
    $endgroup$
    – Mike Battaglia
    Mar 8 at 20:47










  • $begingroup$
    Ahh, I missed that distinction. Thank you!
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Mar 8 at 20:50










  • $begingroup$
    I've never seen this axiom before. Does the family itself need to be a set or can it be a proper class?
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Shore
    Mar 8 at 20:55










  • $begingroup$
    Google suggests this: settheory.mathtalks.org/andreas-blass-well-ordered-choice
    $endgroup$
    – Carl Mummert
    Mar 8 at 20:56













11












11








11


1



$begingroup$


I sometimes see references to the "Axiom of Well-Ordered Choice," but I'm not sure how strong it is. It states that every well-ordered family of sets has a choice function.



By "well-ordered family," I don't mean that the sets within the family are well-ordered, but that the family must index all the sets within the family by some ordinal.



How strong is this axiom? Can it prove the Hahn-Banach theorem, the ultrafilter lemma, anything about measurable sets, etc? Does it have any implications about what sets can be well-ordered (the reals for instance), or perhaps prove anything about the Hartogs number of sets, etc?



Does anyone have a reference for this?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




I sometimes see references to the "Axiom of Well-Ordered Choice," but I'm not sure how strong it is. It states that every well-ordered family of sets has a choice function.



By "well-ordered family," I don't mean that the sets within the family are well-ordered, but that the family must index all the sets within the family by some ordinal.



How strong is this axiom? Can it prove the Hahn-Banach theorem, the ultrafilter lemma, anything about measurable sets, etc? Does it have any implications about what sets can be well-ordered (the reals for instance), or perhaps prove anything about the Hartogs number of sets, etc?



Does anyone have a reference for this?







set-theory axiom-of-choice foundations well-orders






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Mar 8 at 22:00







Mike Battaglia

















asked Mar 8 at 20:22









Mike BattagliaMike Battaglia

1,6491230




1,6491230











  • $begingroup$
    ...isn't this axiom a consequence of ZF? One can choose the (well-defined, since it's well-ordered) lexicographically least element of each set in the family...
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Mar 8 at 20:46






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    That is a family of well-ordered sets, not a well-ordered family of (arbitrary sets).
    $endgroup$
    – Mike Battaglia
    Mar 8 at 20:47










  • $begingroup$
    Ahh, I missed that distinction. Thank you!
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Mar 8 at 20:50










  • $begingroup$
    I've never seen this axiom before. Does the family itself need to be a set or can it be a proper class?
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Shore
    Mar 8 at 20:55










  • $begingroup$
    Google suggests this: settheory.mathtalks.org/andreas-blass-well-ordered-choice
    $endgroup$
    – Carl Mummert
    Mar 8 at 20:56
















  • $begingroup$
    ...isn't this axiom a consequence of ZF? One can choose the (well-defined, since it's well-ordered) lexicographically least element of each set in the family...
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Mar 8 at 20:46






  • 2




    $begingroup$
    That is a family of well-ordered sets, not a well-ordered family of (arbitrary sets).
    $endgroup$
    – Mike Battaglia
    Mar 8 at 20:47










  • $begingroup$
    Ahh, I missed that distinction. Thank you!
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Mar 8 at 20:50










  • $begingroup$
    I've never seen this axiom before. Does the family itself need to be a set or can it be a proper class?
    $endgroup$
    – Robert Shore
    Mar 8 at 20:55










  • $begingroup$
    Google suggests this: settheory.mathtalks.org/andreas-blass-well-ordered-choice
    $endgroup$
    – Carl Mummert
    Mar 8 at 20:56















$begingroup$
...isn't this axiom a consequence of ZF? One can choose the (well-defined, since it's well-ordered) lexicographically least element of each set in the family...
$endgroup$
– Steven Stadnicki
Mar 8 at 20:46




$begingroup$
...isn't this axiom a consequence of ZF? One can choose the (well-defined, since it's well-ordered) lexicographically least element of each set in the family...
$endgroup$
– Steven Stadnicki
Mar 8 at 20:46




2




2




$begingroup$
That is a family of well-ordered sets, not a well-ordered family of (arbitrary sets).
$endgroup$
– Mike Battaglia
Mar 8 at 20:47




$begingroup$
That is a family of well-ordered sets, not a well-ordered family of (arbitrary sets).
$endgroup$
– Mike Battaglia
Mar 8 at 20:47












$begingroup$
Ahh, I missed that distinction. Thank you!
$endgroup$
– Steven Stadnicki
Mar 8 at 20:50




$begingroup$
Ahh, I missed that distinction. Thank you!
$endgroup$
– Steven Stadnicki
Mar 8 at 20:50












$begingroup$
I've never seen this axiom before. Does the family itself need to be a set or can it be a proper class?
$endgroup$
– Robert Shore
Mar 8 at 20:55




$begingroup$
I've never seen this axiom before. Does the family itself need to be a set or can it be a proper class?
$endgroup$
– Robert Shore
Mar 8 at 20:55












$begingroup$
Google suggests this: settheory.mathtalks.org/andreas-blass-well-ordered-choice
$endgroup$
– Carl Mummert
Mar 8 at 20:56




$begingroup$
Google suggests this: settheory.mathtalks.org/andreas-blass-well-ordered-choice
$endgroup$
– Carl Mummert
Mar 8 at 20:56










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes


















9












$begingroup$

The axiom of well-ordered choice, or $sf AC_rm WO$, is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice itself. If we start with $L$ and add $omega_1$ Cohen reals, then go to $L(Bbb R)$, one can show that $sf AC_rm WO$ holds, while $Bbb R$ cannot be well-ordered there.



Pincus proved in the 1970s that this is equivalent to the following statement on Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers:




$sf AC_rm WO$ is equivalent to the statement $forall x.aleph(x)=aleph^*(x)$.




Here, the Lindenbaum number, $aleph^*(x)$, is the least ordinal which $x$ cannot be mapped onto. One obvious fact is that $aleph(x)leqaleph^*(x)$.



In the late 1950s or early 1960s Jensen proved that this assumption also implies $sf DC$. This is also a very clever proof.



The conjunction of these two consequences gives us that $aleph_1leq 2^aleph_0$, as a result of a theorem of Shelah from the 1980s, this implies there is a non-measurable set of reals.



As far as Hahn–Banach, or other things of that sort, I do not believe that much is known on the topic. But to sum up, this axiom does not imply that the reals are well-ordered, but it does imply there is a non-measurable set of reals because there is a set of reals of size $aleph_1$ and $sf DC$ holds. Moreover, it is equivalent to saying that the Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers are equal for all sets.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Do you have a source for a proof of $sf AC_rm WOiff forall x(aleph(x)=aleph^*(x))$?
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 8 at 23:14







  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @Holo karagila.org/2014/on-the-partition-principle
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 8 at 23:26











  • $begingroup$
    (The proof there assumes PP, but really you only use that for maps onto ordinals, which is the same as saying $aleph=aleph^*$.)
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 9 at 8:52










  • $begingroup$
    thank you very much!
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 9 at 16:43











Your Answer








StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);













draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3140508%2fhow-strong-is-the-axiom-of-well-ordered-choice%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









9












$begingroup$

The axiom of well-ordered choice, or $sf AC_rm WO$, is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice itself. If we start with $L$ and add $omega_1$ Cohen reals, then go to $L(Bbb R)$, one can show that $sf AC_rm WO$ holds, while $Bbb R$ cannot be well-ordered there.



Pincus proved in the 1970s that this is equivalent to the following statement on Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers:




$sf AC_rm WO$ is equivalent to the statement $forall x.aleph(x)=aleph^*(x)$.




Here, the Lindenbaum number, $aleph^*(x)$, is the least ordinal which $x$ cannot be mapped onto. One obvious fact is that $aleph(x)leqaleph^*(x)$.



In the late 1950s or early 1960s Jensen proved that this assumption also implies $sf DC$. This is also a very clever proof.



The conjunction of these two consequences gives us that $aleph_1leq 2^aleph_0$, as a result of a theorem of Shelah from the 1980s, this implies there is a non-measurable set of reals.



As far as Hahn–Banach, or other things of that sort, I do not believe that much is known on the topic. But to sum up, this axiom does not imply that the reals are well-ordered, but it does imply there is a non-measurable set of reals because there is a set of reals of size $aleph_1$ and $sf DC$ holds. Moreover, it is equivalent to saying that the Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers are equal for all sets.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Do you have a source for a proof of $sf AC_rm WOiff forall x(aleph(x)=aleph^*(x))$?
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 8 at 23:14







  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @Holo karagila.org/2014/on-the-partition-principle
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 8 at 23:26











  • $begingroup$
    (The proof there assumes PP, but really you only use that for maps onto ordinals, which is the same as saying $aleph=aleph^*$.)
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 9 at 8:52










  • $begingroup$
    thank you very much!
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 9 at 16:43















9












$begingroup$

The axiom of well-ordered choice, or $sf AC_rm WO$, is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice itself. If we start with $L$ and add $omega_1$ Cohen reals, then go to $L(Bbb R)$, one can show that $sf AC_rm WO$ holds, while $Bbb R$ cannot be well-ordered there.



Pincus proved in the 1970s that this is equivalent to the following statement on Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers:




$sf AC_rm WO$ is equivalent to the statement $forall x.aleph(x)=aleph^*(x)$.




Here, the Lindenbaum number, $aleph^*(x)$, is the least ordinal which $x$ cannot be mapped onto. One obvious fact is that $aleph(x)leqaleph^*(x)$.



In the late 1950s or early 1960s Jensen proved that this assumption also implies $sf DC$. This is also a very clever proof.



The conjunction of these two consequences gives us that $aleph_1leq 2^aleph_0$, as a result of a theorem of Shelah from the 1980s, this implies there is a non-measurable set of reals.



As far as Hahn–Banach, or other things of that sort, I do not believe that much is known on the topic. But to sum up, this axiom does not imply that the reals are well-ordered, but it does imply there is a non-measurable set of reals because there is a set of reals of size $aleph_1$ and $sf DC$ holds. Moreover, it is equivalent to saying that the Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers are equal for all sets.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Do you have a source for a proof of $sf AC_rm WOiff forall x(aleph(x)=aleph^*(x))$?
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 8 at 23:14







  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @Holo karagila.org/2014/on-the-partition-principle
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 8 at 23:26











  • $begingroup$
    (The proof there assumes PP, but really you only use that for maps onto ordinals, which is the same as saying $aleph=aleph^*$.)
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 9 at 8:52










  • $begingroup$
    thank you very much!
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 9 at 16:43













9












9








9





$begingroup$

The axiom of well-ordered choice, or $sf AC_rm WO$, is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice itself. If we start with $L$ and add $omega_1$ Cohen reals, then go to $L(Bbb R)$, one can show that $sf AC_rm WO$ holds, while $Bbb R$ cannot be well-ordered there.



Pincus proved in the 1970s that this is equivalent to the following statement on Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers:




$sf AC_rm WO$ is equivalent to the statement $forall x.aleph(x)=aleph^*(x)$.




Here, the Lindenbaum number, $aleph^*(x)$, is the least ordinal which $x$ cannot be mapped onto. One obvious fact is that $aleph(x)leqaleph^*(x)$.



In the late 1950s or early 1960s Jensen proved that this assumption also implies $sf DC$. This is also a very clever proof.



The conjunction of these two consequences gives us that $aleph_1leq 2^aleph_0$, as a result of a theorem of Shelah from the 1980s, this implies there is a non-measurable set of reals.



As far as Hahn–Banach, or other things of that sort, I do not believe that much is known on the topic. But to sum up, this axiom does not imply that the reals are well-ordered, but it does imply there is a non-measurable set of reals because there is a set of reals of size $aleph_1$ and $sf DC$ holds. Moreover, it is equivalent to saying that the Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers are equal for all sets.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



The axiom of well-ordered choice, or $sf AC_rm WO$, is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice itself. If we start with $L$ and add $omega_1$ Cohen reals, then go to $L(Bbb R)$, one can show that $sf AC_rm WO$ holds, while $Bbb R$ cannot be well-ordered there.



Pincus proved in the 1970s that this is equivalent to the following statement on Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers:




$sf AC_rm WO$ is equivalent to the statement $forall x.aleph(x)=aleph^*(x)$.




Here, the Lindenbaum number, $aleph^*(x)$, is the least ordinal which $x$ cannot be mapped onto. One obvious fact is that $aleph(x)leqaleph^*(x)$.



In the late 1950s or early 1960s Jensen proved that this assumption also implies $sf DC$. This is also a very clever proof.



The conjunction of these two consequences gives us that $aleph_1leq 2^aleph_0$, as a result of a theorem of Shelah from the 1980s, this implies there is a non-measurable set of reals.



As far as Hahn–Banach, or other things of that sort, I do not believe that much is known on the topic. But to sum up, this axiom does not imply that the reals are well-ordered, but it does imply there is a non-measurable set of reals because there is a set of reals of size $aleph_1$ and $sf DC$ holds. Moreover, it is equivalent to saying that the Hartogs and Lindenbaum numbers are equal for all sets.







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered Mar 8 at 22:15









Asaf KaragilaAsaf Karagila

309k33441775




309k33441775











  • $begingroup$
    Do you have a source for a proof of $sf AC_rm WOiff forall x(aleph(x)=aleph^*(x))$?
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 8 at 23:14







  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @Holo karagila.org/2014/on-the-partition-principle
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 8 at 23:26











  • $begingroup$
    (The proof there assumes PP, but really you only use that for maps onto ordinals, which is the same as saying $aleph=aleph^*$.)
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 9 at 8:52










  • $begingroup$
    thank you very much!
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 9 at 16:43
















  • $begingroup$
    Do you have a source for a proof of $sf AC_rm WOiff forall x(aleph(x)=aleph^*(x))$?
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 8 at 23:14







  • 2




    $begingroup$
    @Holo karagila.org/2014/on-the-partition-principle
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 8 at 23:26











  • $begingroup$
    (The proof there assumes PP, but really you only use that for maps onto ordinals, which is the same as saying $aleph=aleph^*$.)
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Mar 9 at 8:52










  • $begingroup$
    thank you very much!
    $endgroup$
    – Holo
    Mar 9 at 16:43















$begingroup$
Do you have a source for a proof of $sf AC_rm WOiff forall x(aleph(x)=aleph^*(x))$?
$endgroup$
– Holo
Mar 8 at 23:14





$begingroup$
Do you have a source for a proof of $sf AC_rm WOiff forall x(aleph(x)=aleph^*(x))$?
$endgroup$
– Holo
Mar 8 at 23:14





2




2




$begingroup$
@Holo karagila.org/2014/on-the-partition-principle
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Mar 8 at 23:26





$begingroup$
@Holo karagila.org/2014/on-the-partition-principle
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Mar 8 at 23:26













$begingroup$
(The proof there assumes PP, but really you only use that for maps onto ordinals, which is the same as saying $aleph=aleph^*$.)
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Mar 9 at 8:52




$begingroup$
(The proof there assumes PP, but really you only use that for maps onto ordinals, which is the same as saying $aleph=aleph^*$.)
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Mar 9 at 8:52












$begingroup$
thank you very much!
$endgroup$
– Holo
Mar 9 at 16:43




$begingroup$
thank you very much!
$endgroup$
– Holo
Mar 9 at 16:43

















draft saved

draft discarded
















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid


  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3140508%2fhow-strong-is-the-axiom-of-well-ordered-choice%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

1928 у кіно

Захаров Федір Захарович

Ель Греко